Math Problem Statement
Suppose that X is a finite set and the decision maker has in mind two oneto-one numerical functions u and v on X. Interpret the following choice procedures in words, and determine whether they lead to choice rules satisfying the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives. (a) Fix a number v ∗ . For any choice problem A ⊂ X, let a ∗ be the maximizer of u over A and b ∗ be the maximizer of v over A. The decision maker chooses a ∗ if v(a ∗ ) ≥ v ∗ and she chooses b ∗ otherwise. (b) Fix u ∗ . For any choice problem A, the DM chooses a ∗ maximizing u if u(a ∗ ) ≥ u ∗ , otherwise she chooses b ∗ maximizing v.
Solution
Problem Interpretation:
We are dealing with a decision maker (DM) choosing from a finite set using two numerical utility functions, and . For any subset (a choice problem), the DM's choices are determined by these functions in specific ways.
(a) Fix a number :
-
Procedure:
- From , the DM first identifies , the option that maximizes over .
- The DM also identifies , the option that maximizes over .
- The DM chooses (the maximizer of ) if .
- If , the DM chooses (the maximizer of ).
-
Does this procedure satisfy the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA)?
- IIA Principle: If the DM chooses an option from a set , and if a subset contains that choice, then the DM should still choose the same option from .
In this case, the procedure violates IIA. Here's why:
- Suppose the DM chooses from the original set because .
- Now, consider a subset where is excluded. If , the DM would have chosen , but since is no longer available in , the DM's choice in could differ from their choice in . This violates IIA since the removal of irrelevant alternatives (those not chosen initially) influences the choice.
(b) Fix :
-
Procedure:
- From , the DM first identifies , the option that maximizes over .
- The DM chooses if .
- If , the DM chooses , the maximizer of over .
-
Does this procedure satisfy the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA)?
- This procedure also violates IIA. Here's why:
- Suppose the DM chooses because . If the set removes but retains , the DM might now choose , even though this wasn't their original choice in . The removal of irrelevant alternatives changes the DM’s choice, violating IIA.
- This procedure also violates IIA. Here's why:
Conclusion:
Neither (a) nor (b) satisfies the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA). Both procedures are dependent on the composition of the choice set, meaning that removing certain options can alter the final decision, even though those removed options weren't originally chosen.
Would you like further clarification on any specific part of the explanation?
Here are some related questions that might help expand on this topic:
- What are the implications of the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives in decision theory?
- How can utility functions be used in real-world decision-making scenarios?
- What are examples of choice procedures that satisfy IIA?
- What are other common axioms in choice theory, and how do they compare to IIA?
- Can you explain how violations of IIA might manifest in practical decision-making situations?
Tip: Always pay close attention to whether a decision rule's outcome depends on the set of available choices, as this often signals a violation of IIA.
Ask a new question for Free
By Image
Drop file here or Click Here to upload
Math Problem Analysis
Mathematical Concepts
Decision Theory
Utility Functions
Choice Procedures
Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives
Formulas
-
Theorems
Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA)
Suitable Grade Level
Undergraduate/Graduate
Related Recommendation
Choice Functions and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives
Does the Coombs Method Satisfy the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives?
Does the Coombs System Satisfy Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA)?
Does the Coombs Method Violate the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA)?
Preferences over Rational Numbers and Utility Functions